|
|
||
Y Variations on the thoughts of a shaman about nature and human purpose
What
to do with nature is something to be contested in the public’s mind. Even in
the face of depletion of the goods and services that flow from present
stocks of natural assets, technology implicitly supports the belief that it
brings safe and sustainable satisfaction of needs and aspirations. Yet a
world of unlimited possibilities is a tricky appeal. It may lead us to
reduce —not increase— the asset base which future generations will inherit.
The trap lies in the idea of “optimal substitutability”. It increases the value of the capital stock available for income generation and is considered at present as an optimal path for accumulating assets. Yet it is possible that in the future, people may find other human potentials to be developed, not necessarily based on more abundant and perfected goods. If so, optimal substitution may no longer be an optimal accumulation path for coming geneeations. Technology in the future may allow people to reverse depletion. But it will be at a cost to those generations upon whom today’s values and parameters are being imposed.
he
setting is a remote provincial capital in
The
wise man’s irony underlines what is common sense: no cure will be found for
society’s ills by eradicating a bush, in this case, the coca bush
Erythroxylon sp.. For the old man eradication is nonsense. In his
mind coca is not just a bush but an ancestral cultural legacy: hundreds of
generations over thousands of years have improved it by purposeful
domestication in response to their particular needs, values and environment.
Its properties are widely valued: there was a time when coca leaves were
universally accepted as trading currency among native peoples in large parts
of
When
the wise man finished, officials answered that they did not ignore the
cultural value of coca and other plants that induce ecstatic experiences,
and expressed their respect for their “restricted cultivation and use” in
the context of certain native groups. One of the more articulate officials
even suggested that the object of their mission would be more properly
referred to with the phrase “crops of illegal use”.
Unfortunately this more proper phrase –which qualifies our intentions and
not a crop as such– has not become widespread. It would help to keep in mind
that an important part of the world we live in today is the product of a
long process of intentional human manipulation and selection of life forms
and their life supporting systems. And it would keep us aware that the crops
we cultivate, the landscapes we live in and even the diseases that make us
ill, express the values, needs and aspirations with which we have shaped our
world.
As
the shaman’s irony made it clear, sustainability has to do with values which
cannot be dealt with as scientific or legalistic “truths”. Dealing with
nature and human development is a matter of learning how to manage needs and
aspirations: our nature as political animals –subjects of both needs
and intentions–, faces us at each moment with the unavoidable condition of
choosing how to transform the world in order to satisfy those needs and
aspirations. So neither the presence nor absence of any given plant or
environment will by itself make the world safer, healthier or more
sustainable.
What
to do with nature is therefore something to be contested in the public’s
mind. At present technology has a strong lead in the contest. The public’s
imagination is permanently captivated by its charms. Particularly in the
face of major or cumulative shocks such as climatic change, war, pestilence,
erosion, or generalised economic failure, technology is essential to satisfy
present and many future needs and aspirations because it continually
increases the size and diversity of the assets from which the goods and
services at our disposal flow. And technology is the main pillar of our
limitless capacity to gain new knowledge. Soon hydrogen powered engines
—that will only emit clean water vapour— will economically replace the dirty
gas guzzling internal combustion engines.
Yet
the blessings which come along with technology are mixed. A world of
unlimited possibilities is a tricky appeal. It may lead to reduce —not
increase— the asset base that future generations will inherit. The trap lies
in the idea of “optimal substitutability”.
Technology implicitly supports the belief that by increasing the intensity
and efficiency with which we use energy and information in our daily lives,
we have found an optimal path to satisfy safely and sustainably our needs
and aspirations. Even in the face of depletion of some goods and services
that flow from the present stock of natural assets, as is the case for
example with fossil fuels. Since
oil and gas may be perfectly substituted by an optimal combination of inputs
that will allow us to use hydrogen instead
—one of the most abundant elements in nature—, then
trading
off the depletion of today’s stock of fossil fuels while we fine-tune the
hydrogen powered engine, may be perfectly acceptable in the public’s mind.
It
might even be considered as desirable. Think for example of the
“dematerialisation” of inputs for industry. Rapeseed, a high yielding crop
with an excellent response to fertilisers, can be modified to produce
vegetal oil with the properties of coconut oil, more valuable and profitable
than rapeseed oil. This not only increases efficiency, which is good for
consumers, but will also generate patent income to finance further research.
This is good for economic growth. Natural strains of coconut palm —that flow
naturally from the earth’s stock of assets— offer no comparable economic
opportunities. No one will deny that it is desirable to conserve natural
strains of coconut, but that does not contest technology’s superior capacity
to generate income by means of more perfected goods and services. Optimal
substitution increases the value of the capital stock available for income
generation. Take this argument a
step further and it is sound to think that technology
represents not
only an optimal path for accumulating assets in the present, but also for
generations in the future.
This
conclusion holds true only as long as future generations continue to
consider that human potential is to be developed by increasing access to
more abundant and perfected goods, such as the modified rapeseed oil
described above. Yet it is possible that in the future people may find other
human potentials to be developed and decide to take up a different set of
parameters to define their needs and aspirations. Say they choose to develop
“immaterial goods”, such as the satisfaction with the global quality and
diversity of the social, cultural and biophysical environment in which they
live. Maybe technology in the future will allow them to reverse depletion.
But it would be at a cost to those generations upon whom today’s values and
parameters are being imposed.
So
“optimal substitutability” affects development opportunities for future
generations. Fortunately the consequences and risks that come along with new
technologies do not go by unchecked by public scrutiny. Critics are ready to
recognise that optimality is an important criterion because it supports
efficiency and so it is valuable to shape our needs and aspirations. But
finding optimums brings with it the narrow scope of the specialised
knowledge used in optimisation. Multiple dimensions of the needs and
aspirations that optimisation intends to serve are usually viewed through
excessively narrow frames: the supposition that innovations are only what
innovators expect them to be leads the parties directly involved with their
development to underrate the inherent risks and social implications of new
technologies. As critics rightly argue, this is why it can be dangerous to
use optimality as the main criterion to shape our present and future lives
and environment. And why they stress that it is not reasonable to expect
that technology developers will discover the risks and implication of their
own inventions.
A
cause for worry is the fact that the public in general is shrugging away
from forming balanced views on issues about what should or should not be
done with technology and nature. Conveniently the man on the street is
labelling the issue as “too complex” and leaving the matter for lawmakers or
government officials to decide. What is at stake is how we judge society’s
present path of accumulation: does it generate negative externalities that
will affect people living elsewhere on the globe as well as future
generations? Is it acceptable to suppose that what we consider as “positive”
externalities in the present, will be valued in the same way everywhere and
at all times? These questions are not new. Native American Indians had them
in mind when they replied to a U.S government offer to buy their land in the
19th century. Their reply: the world we have at hand is merely on
loan to us, and we must make sure we hand it down to coming generations with
no irreversible choices already taken for them.
Yet
today it is more difficult for us to make judgments based on the
reversibility criterion, because technological advancement is permanently
modifying what was previously thought irreversible. This is the reason why
it is not accurate to measure sustainability by measuring resource
availability and depletion in physical terms. In principle, however it is
desirable to have some measure to allow each generation to judge if it is
passing on to the next its natural and man made resource base without
impairment. Having such parameters would give future generations a chance to
have an equal vote in the selection of their own goals for human development
and path for resource allocation. A number of management options have been
proposed for this, among them, ideas such as orienting technological
progress towards understanding and management of renewable resources more
efficiently, exploitation of non-renewable resources at a rate equal to the
creation of renewable substitutes, and fostering diversity of belief
systems, environmental systems, organisational systems and knowledge
systems, in order to increase our overall capacity to adapt to the many
possible future scenarios for our world.
All of which brings us to a final reflection derived
form our shaman’s thoughts about nature and human purpose: values and
intentions that may be sustainable in certain cultural and environmental
contexts are not universally sustainable. Plants such as coca and other
plants that induce ecstatic experiences have been a central element of
order, identity and cohesion in the context of native people all over the
world. Yet their products have become poisonous venom in other cultural
contexts. Naturally, the opposite can be expected to have similar effects:
central elements of order, identity and cohesion in “normal” Western
countries, may have perverse effects when imposed upon other societies.
Ò
|
|||